there are many versions of proving completeness theorem for FOL which is proved by godel first in his thesis. but we'll not see the version by godel, but by henkin which is universally introduced in any logic book(but our proof is modified some). basically, we'll prove
(i) any consistent Γ in countable language can be extended to maximal consistent set Δ in given launage;
(ii) Δ is satisfiable.
now go through proof for completeness theorem for FOL in countable language.
(I) Let any set Γ of formulas is consistent in countable language L. define L′=L∪{ci|i<ω} where ci is new constant symbol does not occur in L. then Γ is consistent in L′.
proof : suppose not. then Γ⊢α∧¬α in L′. then we get Γ⊢αcy∧¬αcy by generalization on constants. since every formula is finite, we can eliminate every new constant c introduced in L′(and c is replaced by a variable). thus we get Γ⊢αcy∧¬αcy in L(since every new c is eliminated, this deduction in L′ equals L). this yields contradiction.
now add the formula for every formula φ in L′, ∃xφ→φxc to Γ(this formula will do some useful operations later).
define Θn+1=Θn;θn+1 where θn=(∃xnφn→φxncn) and in Θn+1, cn+1 is the first new constant symbol in L′such that does not occur in Θn and φn+1(fixed enumeration is always possible since we're dealing with countable language). define Θ=∪n∈NΘn. then Γ∪Θ is consistent.
proof : suppose not. then Γ∪Θ⊢φ∧¬φ. then we get Γ∪Θm+1⊢φ∧¬φ. thus Γ∪Θm+1 is inconsistent(and we can take the smallest m≥0). then by RAA, Γ∪Θm⊢θm+1. then by rule T, we get Γ∪Θm⊢∃xφn+1 and Γ∪Θm⊢¬φxn+1cn+1. then by generalization on constants(actually its collorary), we get Γ∪Θm⊢¬∃xφn+1. thus Γ∪Θm is inconsistent which is contradiction to leastness of m.
now construct maximal consistent set Δ for L′. suppose we are given enumeration of every formula φ(this is possible since our language is countable) in L′. define Δn+1=Δn;φn+1if consistent,orΔn;¬φn+1otherwise where Δ0=Γ∪Θ. define Δ=∪n∈NΔn. then Δi for any i∈N and Δ is consistent.
proof for Δi : let Δi is consistent and Δi;φi+1,Δi;¬φi+1 are inconsistent. thus we get Δi⊢φi+1 and Δi⊢¬φi+1. this yields contradiction. and since Δ0=Γ∪Θ is consistent, Δi for any i∈N is consistent.
proof for Δ : suppose not. then we get Δ′⊆Δ finite and inconsistent. since Δ′ is finite, we can enumerate every member of Δ′ and find φ′ which is last member of some Δk. then trivially Δ′⊆Δk. thus we get Δk is inconsistent which is contradiction.
clearly only one of these holds; φ∈Δ or ¬φ∈Δ(if not it is inconsistent).
now claim that φΔ⟺Δ⊢φ. right-side condition is trivial.
for the left side,
Δ⊢φ⇒Δ⊬¬φ(consistency)
⇒¬φ∉Δ
⇒φ∈Δ.
now we'll make some variable assignment and structure which satisfies Δ(actually, we'll construct two structures; one for preliminary for the other structure). define A for L′,
(i) |A| is the set of all terms in L′
(ii) <t1,t2>∈EA iff t1=t2∈Δ
(iii)<t1,…,tn>∈PA iff Pt1…tn∈Δ
(iv) fA(t1,…,tn)=ft1…tn
(v) c=cA and s(x)=x(thus trivially ˉs(t)=t)
A is preliminary structure for B which'll satisfy Δ. intuitive idea for this is similar to compactness theorem for PL(review the idea at compactness theorem for PL. see the idea for satisfaction of Δ). but different thing is about E. since we cannot notice equality symbol('=') in that idea, we've to introduce binary predicate E like above. and notation for E is, tEt′⟺<ˉs(t′),ˉx(t′)>∈EC where C is some given structure).
unfortunately, we observe that in this structure, '=' is not satisfied. considering our semantical definition of ⊨At1=t2[s] iff ˉs(t1)=ˉs(t2), we cannot express E like this. that is, if (t=u)∈Γ⊆Δ, then <t,u>∈EA. and we don't have clue to transform this to ˉs(t)=ˉs(u).
thus we've to make some structure such that tEt′ iff ˉs(t)=ˉs(t′). for this, we'll use the property of E being made by equality symbol the equivalent relation(idea is to make tEt′ iff [t]=[t′], which is some basic set theoretic knowledge. you can prove this easily using equality theorem;see syntax(2). I'll leave this.).
now define equivalence class on A [t]={t′|tEt′}(observe that [t]=[t′]⟺tEt′(this is set-theoretic concept). now define structure B which will satisfy Δ. define B as below.
(i) |B|= the set of all equivalence classes of A on E.
(ii)<[t1],…,[tn]>∈PB iff <t1,…,tn>∈PA
(iii) fB([t1],…,[tn])=[fA(t1,…,tn)]
(iv) cB=[cA] and s(x)=[x](thus ˉs(t)=[t])
now check expected property is met.
α∈Δ iff <t,t′>∈EA iff [t]=[t′] iff <ˉs(t),ˉs(t′)>∈EB iff ⊨Bt=t′[s] where α is the form of t=t′. thus remainer is clear.
now we'll prove φ∈Δ⟺⊨Bφ[s] by induction on the number of ¬, →,∀ in φ.
(i) φ is atomic formula.
(a) φ is t=t′. proved by above fact.
(b) φ is Pt1…tn. then,
Pt1…tn∈Δ iff <t1,…,tn>∈PA iff <[t1],…,[tn]>∈PB iff ⊨BPt1…tn[s]
(ii) φ=¬ϕ.
ϕ∈Δ iff ⊨Bϕ[s] and this is equivalent to
ϕ∉Δ iff ⊭Bϕ[s] thus by definition of satisfaction and Δ property,
¬ϕ∈Δ iff ⊨B¬ϕ[s] thus
φ∈Δ⟺⊨Bφ[s]
(iii) φ=ϕ→ψ.
ϕ→ψ∈Δ iff Δ⊢ϕ→ψ iff ¬ϕ∈Δ∨ψ∈Δ(if not trivial, you can prove this by constructing contradiction) iff ⊨B¬ϕ[s]∨⊨Bψ[s] iff ⊨B(ϕ→ψ)[s]. thus
φ∈Δ⟺⊨Bφ[s]
(iv)φ=∀xϕ.
(a) right-side part. use contraposition.
⊭B∀xϕ[s]⇒⊭Bϕ[s(x|[t])] for some [t]∈|B|
⇒⊭Bψ[s(x|[t])] by alphabetic variants&soundness theorem
⇒⊭Bψxt[s] by substitution lemma
⇒ψxt∉Δ by inductive hypothesis
⇒∀xψ∉Δ(axiom group2)
⇒∀xϕ∉Δ alphabetic variants&soundness
(b)left-side part.
⊨B∀xϕ[s]⇒⊨Bϕ[s(x|[c])] for some [c]∈|B|
⇒⊨Bϕxc[s] by substitution lemma
⇒ϕxc∈Δ by inductive hypothesis
⇒∀xϕ∈Δ by (∃x¬ϕ→¬ϕxc)∈Δ
last part is the form of ∃xψ→ψxc we introduced where ψ is any ψ in L′
thus φ∈Δ⟺⊨Bφ[s]. then since Γ⊆Δ, we have every member of Γ which is satisfiable in L′. then restrict B to L. Γ is satisfiable in L also.
※ φ∈Δ⟺⊨Bφ[s]에 대한 induction에 주의하시길 바랍니다. ¬, →, ∀의 개수에 대해서 induction이 사용됩니다. 말하자면, 총 n개의 ¬, →, ∀를 지닌 임의의 φ에 대해서 inductive hypothesis를 사용하고 (n+1)에 대해서 위의 성질이 성립함을 증명하는 것임을 유의하시길 바랍니다.
※증명은 이걸로 끝이긴 하지만, 아무리 생각해도 쉽게 설명하기가 어렵네요.. 아무래도 집합론을 어느 정도 전제하지 않고는 설명하기가.. 여튼 completeness까지 끝났으니 앞으론 조금 쉬었다가 돌아오겠습니다.